000 | 01883nam a2200337 i 4500 | ||
---|---|---|---|
001 | EDZ0001810658 | ||
003 | StDuBDS | ||
005 | 20220730121953.0 | ||
006 | m||||||||d|||||||| | ||
007 | cr ||||||||||| | ||
008 | 170818r20182017enkb fob 001|0|eng|d | ||
020 | _a9780191851704 | ||
040 |
_aStDuBDS _beng _cStDuBDS _erda _epn |
||
050 | 4 | _aK721.5 | |
082 | 0 | 4 |
_a330.1709 _223 _bLE- |
245 | 0 | 0 |
_aLegalism _bproperty and ownership |
260 |
_c2018 _aNew York _bOxford University Press |
||
300 |
_a1 online resource : _bmaps (black and white) |
||
500 | _aThis edition previously issued in print: 2017. | ||
504 | _aIncludes bibliographical references and index. | ||
520 | 8 | _aIn this volume, ownership is defined as the simple fact of being able to describe something as 'mine' or 'yours', and property is distinguished as the discursive field which allows the articulation of attendant rights, relationships, and obligations. Property is often articulated through legalism as a way of thinking that appeals to rules and to generalizing concepts as a way of understanding, responding to, and managing the world around one. An Aristotelian perspective suggests that ownership is the natural state of things and a prerequisite of a true sense of self. An alternative perspective from legal theory puts law at the heart of the origins of property. However, both these points of view are problematic in a wider context, the latter because it rests heavily on Roman law. | |
521 | _aSpecialized. | ||
650 | 0 |
_aRight of property _xHistory. _968393 |
|
650 | 0 |
_aProperty (Roman law) _924971 |
|
700 | 1 |
_aKantor, Georgy _994687 |
|
700 | 1 |
_aLambert, T B _994688 |
|
700 | 1 |
_aSkoda, Hannah _994689 |
|
776 | 0 | 8 |
_iPrint version : _z9780198813415 |
856 | 4 | 0 |
_3Oxford scholarship online _uhttp://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198813415.001.0001 |
942 |
_2ddc _cEBK |
||
999 |
_c1281170 _d1281170 |